Peirce’s Pragmatic Maxim as a Logical Consequence of Semiotic Idealism
DOI:
https://doi.org/10.14394/filnau.2018.0008Słowa kluczowe:
Peirce, semiotic idealism, Kant, phenomenalism, pragmatismAbstrakt
The purpose of this paper is to show that the pragmatic maxim can be construed as a logical consequence of semiotic idealism. Peirce proposed his semiotic idealism in the 1860s and based it on two premises: first, that we could know only symbols and, second, that the only things that exist are those that could be known. From these premises, he concluded that only symbols exist. This conception was meant to refute the distinction between the substance and its phenomenal manifestations. If semiotic idealism implies the pragmatic maxim, then it becomes clear why the pragmatic maxim says that the conception of the effects of the object is the conception of the object: it is because Peirce thought that the effects are the object. Furthermore, the close link between these conceptions may account for Peirce’s prolonged silence about pragmatism.
Bibliografia
Apel K.-O. (1995), Charles S. Peirce: From Pragmatism to Pragmaticism, trans. J. M. Krois, New York: Humanity Books.
Bellucci F. (2016), "Inferences from Signs: Peirce and the Recovery of the shmeiªon ", Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 52(1), 259-284. https://doi.org/10.2979/trancharpeirsoc.52.2.08
Gava G. (2014), Peirce's Account of Purposefulness: A Kantian Perspective, New York: Routledge. https://doi.org/10.4324/9781315849577
McCarthy J. E. (1984), "Semiotic Idealism", Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society 20(4), 395-433.
Murphey M. G. (1993), The Development of Peirce's Philosophy, Indianapolis–Cambridge: Hackett Publishing Company.
Parker K. A. (1998), The Continuity of Peirce's Thought, Nashville: Vanderbilt University Press.
Savan D. (1983), "Toward a Refutation of Semiotic Idealism", Semiotic Inquiry 3, 1-8.
Short T. L. (2007), Peirce's Theory of Signs, Cambridge: Cambridge University Press. https://doi.org/10.1017/CBO9780511498350